Categories
On the Environment

The Earth, You, and the Economy pt. 4: Conclusion

Throughout the recorded history of the human species, several societies have faced existential crises that mandated major cultural shifts in opinion and philosophical outlook. In fact, I would argue that all major philosophical paradigm shifts have coincided with major social upheaval and crisis. The most recent and poignant example of such a shift was the advent of the postmodern era as a reaction against modernism. The beginning of the end for modern thought was the advent of nuclear technologies. As the Cold War progressed and people were faced with a growing insecurity in their existence brought about by the nuclear arms race and the ability of few to destroy many, the flaws of modern thought became progressively apparent.

Today, we have come to face a similar crisis, and in fact the crises that brought about the advent of postmodernism overlaps significantly with the crises that may end it. Since the Industrial Revolution, we have been steadily increasing in number and carbon output due to over-consumption of goods. This increased carbon output has steadily warmed the globe through the greenhouse effect, and if we do not stop it, the effects of climate change will be devastating to humans in coastal and warmer areas. Despite overwhelming scientific consensus on the matter, some still cling to ignorance regarding our culpability for this problem.

Climate change is an issue of major contention amongst politically engaged individuals in America and across the globe. The question of climate change, its relationship to human activity, and policies surrounding environmental concerns raises deeper questions about the nature of truth, the specter of modern philosophy in today’s technology, and our ethical responsibilities regarding the planet. Humanity is facing its first crisis that threatens the existence of not only our culture locally, but our survival as a species. A change in cultural attitude will either rise up to meet the challenges posed by climate change, or we will die out and the questions raised will no longer require an answer.

The global atmosphere and climate are a public, common good insomuch that no one may claim ownership of them; this means that the problem of climate change can be understood through a version of the Prisoners’ Dilemma known as the tragedy of the commons. The tragedy starts with two basic premises: 1) it is in everyone’s best interest to maintain and preserve common goods so that they are not exhausted, and 2) everyone can benefit individually from exploiting common goods. If the lesson taught by the Prisoners’ Dilemma is followed, that as individuals it is in our best interest to act selfishly, and we do not change our approach to such ethical topics as to consider more than our individual well-being, then the tragedy plays out as it is named, tragically, with the common good being exhausted completely.

The developed nations of the world have been the largest beneficiaries to greenhouse gas emissions, and have contributed the most to anthropogenic climate change. This seems to suggest that, when splitting the bill for climate change mitigation, the largest portion (nearly all) of the bill should be passed to the Western, developed nations, especially the United States. The issue with this approach is that the Western world, in contributing to greenhouse emissions, has also built the largest economy, and with that, has assembled the most political power. Any international political power looking to mitigate climate change must offer up solutions that developed nations would agree to participate in, and if a solution demands that the developed world pay its fair share towards mitigating climate change, there is little hope of ever getting the cooperation of nations like the United States. This politically aware approach demands an even more prudent solution due to the “America First” rhetoric of the Trump administration. Despite growing scientific evidence supporting the conclusion that climate change is anthropogenic and a threat to human survival, the epistemic surety of the United States has fallen into such disarray that at least enough of the public does not believe in scientific evidence supporting anthropogenic climate change to elect a climate change denier into the office of the President. As such, a brief examination of climate evidence is mandated by our current political climate.

In search of a valid source that supports the existence of anthropogenic climate change, one need not look far. In my research on the topic I found a total of zero sources claiming anything other than anthropogenic climate change, and these sources date back to at least 1991, when Shell (the oil company) produced a documentary called Climate of Concern, reporting on U.N. and in-company research about the effects burning fossil fuels have on the global temperature. Despite being publicly aware of climate change concerns, Shell and other oil companies continued to invest heavily in oil production. Some oil companies have even hired the same research firms who raised doubts about the health effects of smoking to create reports designed to raise doubts as to whether climate change is anthropogenic. [1]

In response to further bleak reports on climate change, the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) was formed to create an authority consensus on climate change and its effects. This panel has significant input from countries with high interest in the success of the fossil fuel industry like the United States and Russia, but in spite of this conflict of interest, the IPCC still reports a bleak outlook if nothing is done about our carbon emissions.[2] Furthermore, we are now witnessing the effects of climate change on local markets and agriculture. The production of maple syrup has slowed considerably in the northeast United States, where maple syrup used to be a large agricultural force. Now, the industry has been forced northward into Canada, where the climate has warmed enough to make maple syrup production more economically viable.[3]

Several international agreements have been made regarding the mitigation of climate change in the past. The first of these was the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC) in 1992, which provided the groundwork for other international agreements to be made. The second was the Kyoto Protocol in 1997, which extended the UNFCCC and provided emissions targets to member countries, the United States failed to ratify it in the Senate. The last, and most recently famous, is the Paris Agreement. The Paris Agreement does not mandate a punishment for member countries that fail to meet emissions regulations, but it does require that member countries analyze and report the findings on their domestic emissions and their relationship to the goals of the UNFCCC. The United States pulled out of the Paris Agreement because of a question regarding how our membership was ratified. Nonetheless, these international efforts, while moving us in the correct direction, have done very little to move us towards solving the issue at hand, especially without cooperation from the United States.[4]

The arguments that normally revolve around the topic of climate change raise questions as to whether we can really be certain of anything we hear secondhand and do not experience ourselves. This distinctively postmodern mindset being applied to such an existential crisis has led to a sudden awareness of the failures of postmodernism in providing enough guidance to the mostly unphilosophical public in terms of action and truth. Postmodernism works in such a crisis only if everyone is equally informed, otherwise it ensures that we can never agree enough to work together. Unfortunately, the primary reactions to this realization of the failures of postmodernism in guiding the uninformed have been either a re-entrenchment of the fundamentalist modern mindset or a nihilistic skepticism without the counterbalance of the existentialist search for meaning. Neither of these systems of thought alone can provide an adequate solution to climate change, and a new paradigm shift is required if the problem of climate change is to be dealt with.

Before I present my view on this potential paradigm shift, it is necessary to examine two other possible solutions to the problem of climate change. The first of these solutions is that offered by the modern mindset. This solution could be called the superhero, deus ex machina, solution, but the more accurate name for it is the geoengineering solution. This solution requires that we treat the earth’s biosphere as one large, potentially devastating laboratory.[5] We are currently capable of technical, engineered, high-tech solutions to the climate issue, but in order to implement these solutions, we would need to roll the dice on potentially catastrophic outcomes should any factors be unconsidered in predicting how these solutions might affect the biosphere in the long-term. Some of the proposals of the geoengineering solution are injecting the earth’s atmosphere with reflective particles to reflect a portion of sunlight away from the earth, effectively putting a sunshade on the entire planet, allowing us to continue the emissions of greenhouse gases without further warming effects. Other solutions involve satellite arrays which can deploy to reflect sunlight, and carbon removal machines.[6]

The second potential solution is to consider the role of the individual in climate change mitigation. Most people are uninformed about the role they play in climate change and are overwhelmed by the controversy surrounding the topic. Yet, when Trump pulled the United States out of the Paris Agreement, several mayors and local communities voiced that they would still fulfill their obligations to the goals of climate change mitigation. If proper education and discussion on the topic of climate change can rise above the level of heated argument, then people have shown that they desire to be a part of the right side of this issue. No one wants to be the bad guy of the story, even if that means they have to sacrifice. The ethical pressure on individuals to cut back on carbon emissions needs to be made known in a compelling manner. The zero emissions year (year in which we can no longer emit greenhouse gases) for avoiding the bulk of damage that would be caused by continued emission of anthropogenic greenhouse gases is fast approaching, in fact it is somewhere between 2030 and 2050, depending on how quickly we cut back on our emissions now. If we cut back more now, it allows us a greater amount of greenhouse gas emissions in the future, buying us precious time in which to find a better solution. We each have a role to play in maintaining a lean carbon budget for the betterment of future mankind, and the cause of the problem in the first place, while almost entirely corporate greed, is also due to complicit individuals and conspicuous consumption.[7]

Joseph Grange presents a peculiar amalgamation of American philosophy and Confucianism in his article, Healing the Planet. He argues that both Western and Eastern philosophies contain, within their past, the philosophical toolkit necessary to properly address the issue of global warming. This toolkit can be found in the American philosophical approach to ethics in that, finding little value in empirically-based ethics that cannot reach beyond nihilism, most American philosophy looks to aesthetics to shape our ethics. This view is best expressed by Charles Saunders Pierce, who regarded aesthetics as the ground of ethics, epistemology, and even logic. Thus, feeling, which is the driving principle behind aesthetics, also becomes the ground of intelligence. Knowledge without praxis (the embodiment/actualization of knowledge) is not intelligence.[8]

Thus, Western philosophy provides a framework for understanding Confucian non-dualism in today’s context. Confucius places the role of knowledge in intimate conversation with that of feeling in his idea of xin, the heartmind.[9] On each side of the conflict caused by climate change we see a form of dualism that has ceased to be helpful in our context of potential risk to human existence. The artificial division between us and our environment hinders our ability to see how small daily decisions relate to the systematic exploitation of the environment. Our interdependence on our environment goes further than merely our material sustenance. Our very consciousness and identity arises because of our consideration of that which is not us (our environment), and thus our identity is the gap between us and our environment. To say it briefly, our consciousness is the space between that which we are, and that which we are not. Without both of these components, we are nothing.

This non-dualism applies to the situation of climate change in several different ways. It provides a foundation for claiming earth-care as an ethical duty, since the border between individual and nature is no longer clear in non-dualism. This paradigm shift is mere speculation, but no other ethical system can adequately answer the questions raised by anthropogenic climate change. Non-dualism provides a basis to rethink our relationship with each other as well as with property and consumption. Ignoring climate change is no longer a viable option in non-dualism, let alone an ethical one.

Works Cited:

Deady, Erin L. “Why the Law of Climate Change Matters: From Paris to a Local Government Near You.” The Florida Bar Journal 91, no. 9 (2017): 54-58. Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).

Fuente, de la Alberto, Rojas, Maisa, and Lean, Claudia Mac. “A human-scale perspective on global warming: Zero emission year and personal quotas.” The Public Library of Science One 12, no. 6 (2017): 1-16. Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).

Grange, Joseph. “Healing the Planet.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 40 (2013): 251-269. Philosopher’s Index, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).

Romar, Edward J. “Snapshots of the Future: Darfur, Katrina, and Maple Sugar (Climate Change, the Less Well-Off and Business Ethics).” Journal of Business Ethics 85, (2009): 121-132. Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).

Steadman, Hugh. “Climate Catastrophe.” New Zealand International Review 42, no. 4 (2017): 19-23. Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).

Stilgoe, Jack. “Geoengineering as Collective Experimentation.” Science and Engineering Ethics 22, no. 3 (2016): 851-869. Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).

  1. Hugh Steadman, “Climate Catastrophe,” New Zealand International Review 42, no. 4 (2017): 19-23, Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).
  2. Hugh Steadman, “Climate Catastrophe,” New Zealand International Review 42, no. 4 (2017): 19-23, Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).
  3. Edward J. Romar, “Snapshots of the Future: Darfur, Katrina, and Maple Sugar (Climate Change, the Less Well-Off and Business Ethics),” Journal of Business Ethics 85, (2009): 121-132, Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).
  4. Erin L. Deady, “Why the Law of Climate Change Matters: From Paris to a Local Government Near You,” The Florida Bar Journal 91, no. 9 (2017): 54-58, Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).
  5. Jack Stilgoe, “Geoengineering as Collective Experimentation,” Science and Engineering Ethics 22, no. 3 (2016): 851-869, Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).
  6. Jack Stilgoe, “Geoengineering as Collective Experimentation,” Science and Engineering Ethics 22, no. 3 (2016): 851-869, Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).
  7. Alberto de la Fuente, Maisa Rojas, and Claudia Mac Lean, “A human-scale perspective on global warming: Zero emission year and personal quotas,” The Public Library of Science One 12, no. 6 (2017): 1-16, Academic Search Complete, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).
  8. Joseph Grange, “Healing the Planet,” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 40 (2013): 251-269, Philosopher’s Index, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).
  9. Joseph Grange, “Healing the Planet,” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 40 (2013): 251-269, Philosopher’s Index, EBSCOhost (accessed November 15, 2017).
Categories
On the Environment

The Earth, You, and the Economy pt. 3

“In activity man feels himself free, unlimited, happy. Activity is the positive side of one’s personality…. And the happiest, the most blissful activity is that which is productive…. Hence this attribute of the species – productive activity – is assigned to God; that is, realized and made objective as divine activity.” – Ludwig Feuerbach

.   .   .

“God blessed them and said to them, ‘Be fruitful and increase in number; fill the Earth and subdue it. Rule over the fish in the sea and the birds in the sky and over every living creature that moves on the ground.’ Then God said, ‘I give you every seed bearing plant on the face of the whole Earth and every tree that has fruit with seed in it. They will be yours for food. And to all the beasts of the Earth and all the birds of the sky and all the creatures that move on the ground – everything that has the breath of life in it – I give every green plant for food.’ And it was so.” – Genesis 1:28-30

.   .   .

 “Then he said, ‘This is what I’ll do. I will tear down my barns and build bigger ones, and there I will store my surplus grain. 19 And I’ll say to myself, “You have plenty of grain laid up for many years. Take life easy; eat, drink and be merry.”’“But God said to him, ‘You fool! This very night your life will be demanded from you. Then who will get what you have prepared for yourself?’“This is how it will be with whoever stores up things for themselves but is not rich toward God.” – Luke 12:18-21

.   .   .

If you see the poor oppressed in a district, and justice and rights denied, do not be surprised at such things; for one official is eyed by a higher one, and over them both are others higher still. The increase from the land is taken by all; the king himself profits from the fields.

Whoever loves money never has enough;
    whoever loves wealth is never satisfied with their income.
    This too is meaningless.

As goods increase,
    so do those who consume them.
And what benefit are they to the owners
    except to feast their eyes on them?

The sleep of a laborer is sweet,
    whether they eat little or much,
but as for the rich, their abundance
    permits them no sleep.

I have seen a grievous evil under the sun:

wealth hoarded to the harm of its owners,
    or wealth lost through some misfortune,
so that when they have children
    there is nothing left for them to inherit.
Everyone comes naked from their mother’s womb,
    and as everyone comes, so they depart.
They take nothing from their toil
    that they can carry in their hands.

This too is a grievous evil:

As everyone comes, so they depart,
    and what do they gain,
    since they toil for the wind?
All their days they eat in darkness,
    with great frustration, affliction and anger.” – Ecclesiastes 5:8-17

.   .   .

“Experience demonstrates that there may be a slavery of wages only a little less galling and crushing in its effects than chattel slavery, and that this slavery of wages must go down with the other.” – Frederick Douglass

.   .   .

Normally I would not begin with so many quotes, but why say it differently when it has been said so clearly already? Let me explain why I have chosen these quotes.

Everyone feels in themselves their worth when they are at work. This is what ties us most directly to humanity, because what makes us distinctively human is our ability to bring order out of disorder. To apply category, logic, reason, and purpose to indifferent objects is the uniquely human task set to us by God in Genesis. We name the animals, categorize them to better understand them, how and why they were made, and it is for our survival and enrichment that we cultivate the Earth. If there were no humans to do this work, existence itself would be meaningless. We are the universe understanding itself; made of dust taken from the ground and the stars (proof). Although my last post could be taken to say that this work is a morally negative act, I mean the opposite. What I am attempting to say is that the work itself is good, but the regulation of our relationship to the objects we are stewards of through the economy has turned the work against us. This is because the relationship is no longer stewardly, it is exploitative. We exploit the environment for our personal luxury. We do not cultivate, we own. This is the purpose of the first four quotes.

Now the last quote and the quote from Ecclesiastes start to pick at another aspect of the problem: labor. The way corporate business works in our economy is to destroy the relationship between us and our work, that which God has given to us as our uniquely human task. When you work for someone else for a set wage, the value of your work is always greater than your earnings. Were you to work the exact same job for yourself, you would take home exactly how much you had earned for the corporation. Some will defend this relationship as fair on the grounds that without the corporation the organized work of many would be impossible, and I consent this point. However, I am not saying that everyone working in an organization should earn the same wage, I am saying you should earn what you produce. Jeff Bezos, the world’s richest man, has 114.4 billion dollars. To put that in perspective, if Jeff worked at $15/hr. it would take him 870,624 years of working 24 hours a day, 7 days a week, to earn all of his money. No one can earn that much money, other people earned it for him. In harsher words, Jeff stole other people’s labor. At the end of their last quarter, Walmart made $5.8 billion dollars as a corporation. Those earnings are passed on to the executives and shareholders of Walmart. If Walmart took 3 billion of those earnings and paid it out to their employees, they could give all 2.2 million of their employees a raise of $5,454. This is not annual income, this is quarterly income. This is why Frederick Douglass, a man who intimately knew the evils of slavery, called wage labor slavery.

This goes further. In 2010 the Supreme Court of the United States of America came down on the side of corporations in the historic Citizens United vs. FEC case. This case allowed corporations the unfettered ability to donate to political elections in the name of freedom of speech. Politicians are now able to take massive donations from corporations which do not represent the people. Politicians are now representatives of corporate interests, not that they weren’t before 2010, but it is now official law. The power of the people to stand up to corporations which only want to exploit their labor for the enrichment of their shareholders is null and void. If we want to eat, we must work for the corporations and enable their exploitation of mother Earth. The GDP must grow because if it does not, those with power will not ‘trickle down’ enough money for us to survive. Indeed, people are already dying.

I firmly believe there are ways to do this better, but inaction is getting us nowhere.

Categories
On the Environment

The Earth, You, and the Economy Pt. 2

Gross Domestic Product is a measurement of all economic activity in a given time period and region. Basically, anytime anyone spends money in America, it increases our national GDP. In another frame of mind, GDP represents the exact deduction our economy has made from the ecosystem. Understanding how the GDP works is vital to understanding how our economic choices effect the Earth. This is due to the fact that the value of our currency is directly related to our GDP. Remember that the value of a fiat currency is determined by two factors alone: that we all agree it has value, and what amount of any given commodity a dollar (in the case of America) can buy. There is no real value until the commodity has been bought, thus raising the GDP. GDP is the new version of the gold standard in American economics. If no new bills are printed and GDP rises, it means that the buying power of the dollar has risen, and prices drop. There are not very many new bills introduced in the economy each year, but there are some. Thus, if the GDP doesn’t increase each year, the buying power of a dollar decreases and inflation occurs.

All of this adds up to say that our economy demands that our GDP increase each year. This is a direct result of the entire system that controls almost every aspect of our public lives. Productivity must increase or the system that distributes food, healthcare, housing, clothing, etc., falls apart at the seams very quickly (see the 1930s). So what about dear old mother Earth?

When GDP rises, Earth loses value. That value is added to the economy, but it is frequently used to further insulate us and the system from the ecosystem. This is especially true when that GDP comes from single-use commodities like energy or disposables.  However, even if these single-use commodities were completely done away with we would still be in a system with a definite end: ecological death.

The Earth has a limited amount of value. There’s only so much gold, cobalt, nickel, oil, copper, etc. on the planet. Once that value is completely used, GDP has nowhere to withdraw from, and you end up in a global, ecological depression. On an individual level we can only effect real disruption of this system by refusing to spend money in excess. If we only buy that which we need and forgo luxury the GDP that we contribute decreases. Spend less money, produce less GDP. Unfortunately a decreased GDP does not mean added value to the ecosystem; only if a GDP was negative would it mean that value was actually returned to the ecosystem, but that is impossible. So decreasing our GDP and increasing the portion of the GDP that comes from sustainable practices lengthens the amount of time until the ecological collapse of the Earth, but it does not prevent it. The unfortunate consequence of decreasing the GDP is that those who end up paying the most for the decrease are those who are already without the means to absorb additional costs.

If only there were a way to reconcile our relationship with mother Earth so that we weren’t so abusive of her and each other….

Categories
On the Environment

The Earth, You, and the Economy

The purpose of this post is to introduce some basic principles that will be vital to our consideration of our relationship to the Earth, a topic that has become increasingly important to me the more that I have learned. This relationship has become regulated and controlled by the economy, and thus money and its connection to the planet is the first key idea to understand.

In our country and in the global marketplace we use a peculiar type of currency known as fiat currency. For those who do not remember from their high school civics class, fiat currencies are odd because they have no physical standard of value. Other currencies of the past have been tied to some kind of physical commodity, like gold, silver, or even grain. Thus, if the demand for gold increases, the value of a gold-standard currency increases. However, if gold becomes more available, the value of gold-standard currency decreases. The amount of value in a commodity based economy is dictated by the amount of value in the particular commodity. In other words, commodity economies are regulated by our communal relationship to the commodity. The two major players in this type of system are the Earth, who provides the commodities, and the decentralized will of the people.

Thus, before we switched to a fiat currency system, the dollar had real value because it represented a certain amount of the gold held by the United States government. This gold was essentially owned by the people in the form of the dollar, anybody could own it, and the amount of gold which your particular dollar could be exchanged for was controlled by the amount of bills in the economy and the amount of gold in the U.S. Treasury. In terms of alienation from actual value, commodities themselves are the least alienated because they are identical with the value they represent. Representative currencies are more alienated because their value is artificially controlled by the amount of bills in circulation, and fiat money is the most alienated. Fiat money only has value because the government says that it has value and we all agree to abide by what the government says regarding its value.

This presents the first breakdown in our relationship with Earth. The economy’s job is to distribute commodities among the people. We do not produce commodities by our own work, but in partnership with the Earth. In the end the Earth provides, we simply cultivate and reap according to our needs. In a commodity economy, even if you were not a farmer or miner, your work was directly connected to the Earth. This relationship is reality, even today, we have simply covered over this truth by insulating ourselves from nature. Even programmers are shaping the way physical products behave, much like potters shape clay to perform certain tasks. Teachers of old, who produced nothing and shaped nothing, were still tethered to Earth by the system in which they were paid. No matter how far technology can progress, we will always rely on nature. Fiat currencies hide this reality by untethering our work from Earth in terms of its monetary value. The dollar has no ecological value until it is spent on products derived from the ecosystem.

The point of considering our currency is to find a better, more accurate way of thinking about us and the Earth. It is to start thinking of the goods and services we buy and sell as deductions from the natural environment so that we realize that our wealth is limited by the availability of natural resources.

Categories
On Self

On Self: Nature

Previously, I discussed where we come from. To me, the next fundamental question about self-hood is “what are we made of?”. This question is not one we typically ask about ourselves, but it is an enlightening query; because what we are, like most things about ourselves, is not something we can choose.

Muscle and bone, tendon and tissue, fat and skin, faces and hands and shapes: we are first and foremost bodily beings. Yet, because of the advancements of civilization and the success of our ingenuity, we have little connection between our self identity and our bodily being. We have ironed out many of the experiences that for millennia have placed human consciousness squarely in the life of the body, and as a result have become unattached from our physicality and reliance upon nature. We no longer think regularly about how temperatures, rain, sunlight, and soil are the physically sustaining resource that give us life every day. We consume goods and products with little to no consideration or thankfulness for how they came to be and what it costs to make them.

Think about the computer that you are reading this blog post on. Although it might seem about as unnatural as anything could be, it is bound to nature by the very atoms that compose it. The plastics are refined bits of dead micro-organisms that, many years ago, floated upon the ocean soaking in sunlight and CO2, the glass and silicon chips are basically just refined sand, and the metals were at one point in their life buried beneath dirt and stone. We are much the same way. Although we do not think much about it, the difference between our bodies and the rock we stand on is not in substance but in association. In fact, we are very much the Earth, and the Earth is very much us.

Becoming conscious of what it is the we are made of is not as simple as being told, or else I would have stopped typing in the last paragraph. Instead, it is something that must be re-integrated to our consciousness through experiences and habits. My solution to this is backpacking. By venturing out, away from the comforts of civilization, we are forcefully made aware of the fragility of the bodily self, and jarringly placed into the mindset that my self is my body, and my body is a part of nature. This works better if conditions for backpacking are poor and you’re miserable. Cold rain, limited resources, and no google to search if you don’t know how to do something makes it abundantly clear that we are at the mercy of our knowledge, skill, and the whims of mother nature.

You may be thinking to yourself that I sound like a masochistic lunatic, and I might be, but it is not the misery that most times accompanies backpacking that I love. It is the reward you get for successfully relying on yourself. It is the sense of self-sufficiency, not in the sense that you can do it alone and don’t need others to help you, but rather in the sense that your self can survive when reduced to its bodily components. This reward often takes the form of the peaceful tranquility of morning in the woods and a sense that you, along with the flora and fauna around you, have done a good job in surviving the night. This sense of self-awareness that includes nature is not easily described, so I encourage you to go find a hiking buddy and do it yourself.

We are made of nature, and when we die we contribute our bodies back into nature. Nothing of our career, our education, our hobbies, or our achievements go with us into death. We go back into the Earth. Living in this truth allows us to live more honestly as who we are.

Categories
On Self

On Self: The Origin Story

We have an issue knowing who we are, as previously discussed in my opening post to this series. We spend so much of our time wondering who we are, an ironic task at best, but a brutal journey if engaged with seriously. The problem is, we do not choose who we are. Our self begins to form without our consent and without our input in its earliest roots. Like an acorn planted in a field, we simply grow into ourselves without a choice in where we are planted or whether or not we actually want to grow. Accepting this premise: that the self begins before we are aware of it, is crucial to understanding the self as a whole.

So, where do we begin then?

Birth.

Some might argue that we pre-date birth in our souls, but if this is true, then this soul would not factor into our formation of self anyways because we clearly cannot know anything about ourselves before our bodily existence. Our goal is to know ourselves and about the self as they are now, not as they existed in a bygone age of perfection beyond our capability of understanding. Any such knowledge of a pre-existent soul would be meaningless without an understanding of the self in the present, so the discussion of the supernatural is irrelevant until we can grasp the natural to such a degree as to brush against the supernatural.

So, back to birth. Why does the self begin at birth and not at conception? (This conversation has nothing to do with the rights of a fetus, this is merely about the formation of the self) Before our birth, our bodies and our mother’s bodies are virtually the same. We cannot have any neurological firings that separate us from our mother until we are aware that the world around us is not merely an extension of ourselves. There must be a separation in order for the self to begin. Before birth, the world is a womb and some voices/noises. The environment that shapes our most basic neurological firings is the environment in which we do not have a self.

A sense of self, the sense that is hardwired into the neurology of self-referential loops within our brain, cannot be formed until we recognize that there are others in the world, and the first other we create is our mother. Our brains are forced to take in the information that there is a world besides the womb, and there are others besides ourselves at birth. This recognition draws a hard line between the neurons which have been firing as reactions to the information fed to us in the womb, all of which form a basis for our self, and new neurons which must begin to parse the information our senses are gathering about the new world we find ourselves in. So upon entry into the world outside the womb, we begin to form a self. This is the foundation of the id.

If your reaction to this is to say: “Well, this is a bunch of malarkey, I don’t have any memory of my birth and it doesn’t play a role in the actions I take or who I am.” I would respond that the self is not a cohesive structure that is always in agreement with itself. We have passions and desires that are inherent to our humanity that we do not always want or accept from ourselves. Our birth is the beginning, the root of self, and that root is the one we do not always want to acknowledge or give voice to. It is the id, the underlying instincts and desires that make us human. It is ultimately the desire to be free from the pain of being separate.

The issue with the departure from the mother is that our self is fundamentally dependent on her. Our entire identity as a separate entity from the doctor whose hands we arrived in and the hospital room we suddenly found ourselves in is based entirely upon the neurons that wired together while we were still a part of our mother. We are simultaneously inseparable from mom and irreconcilably separate from her. We can’t be unborn, and we can’t rewrite our existence as a self-existent being. This disgruntled beginning is a fundamental piece to understanding the human condition. We hate being alone in ourselves, but we can never be truly united to others either.

This only becomes worse as our identities become less complex and more defined. This only becomes worse as we develop an ego.

Categories
On Self

On Self: an introduction

There is a lot of talk regarding identity swirling around in popular conversation today. Among my generation much of this conversation is in reference to personality-typing systems like Love Languages, Meier-Briggs, and Strength-finders. At Olivet this conversation is centered around the Enneagram, probably the most philosophically aware personality-typing system when properly understood. All of these conversations claim to be aimed at helping our communities better understand themselves and operate more efficiently, but there is a deeper motivation to these conversations. This motivation deals directly with a key aspect of the human condition, and that is the existence of the self.

We are obsessed with the self. We move away, we go on long trips, we break up relationships, we leave jobs, we start new careers: all in an effort to “find ourselves”. So where does this idea of the self come from? Where are the roots of identity and distinction between persons? What separates me from you? Who are the key players in the game of self-building? What are the pros and cons of self-building? Is any of this differentiation real? What do religion and sociology have to say about it? These questions are the subject of The Cogitator’s series: On Self. 

The study of the self can be quite trippy and deconstructive, so hang on with me as we get into the self-referential nature of these ideas and define key terms.

Self: a reference of an individual to the individuality of the individual making the reference. (see where this gets trippy?)

Ego: the conscious self that seems to be responsible for decision making and accomplishment/failure. This is the operative form of the self; our inner dialogue.

Id: the subconscious self that consists of the underlying mechanisms of our psychology/neurology. The conditioned aspects of our self that we do not have active control over. Our basic drives and instincts.

Consciousness: Another way of referring to the ego/id relationship as a whole, particularly when referring to the social aspects of the self.

None of these definitions are wholly accurate, as the ideas represented by the words are far too complex for a few descriptive sentences, but they give a basic idea of what I mean when I use them. The clarification of these terms is a basic goal of this series. Likewise, these concepts are not necessarily reflective of reality, but they are the way the conversation around self has been framed by countless others, so they are useful.

My engagement with this topic largely comes from the type of art that I enjoy, so I will be making occasional references to these artworks as they intersect our conversation. In fact, it is my belief that all art comes into contact with the question, what is it to be human?, at some level.

Let’s get into ourselves.

Categories
Philosophy

On Wisdom and Morality

Wisdom and Morality are like a married couple. Couples complete each other in a sense, and one is incapable of living up to their full potential apart from the other. Trying to define where one begins and the other stops is a difficult task, but they are only so closely intertwined because of their unique gifts. Couples live to serve the betterment of the other, but must rely on the other to do the same. Wisdom and Morality both implicate our actions day-to-day, but they’re distinct in their approach and need each other to operate correctly. Wisdom is the toolkit by which Morality reaches its end, and Morality is the map by which Wisdom properly navigates the world.

Wisdom by itself is merely the ways in which one achieves success, gains material security, prolongs his/her life, and navigates cultural mores and norms. In our culture we consider the wisest to be the most economically successful, and the evidence for this is everywhere. Consider who’s books we look to for life-advice and leadership. Our government is outstandingly populated by former business men, all of whom are seen as having been successful. Our pastors-in-training frequently hold MBAs instead of MDivs; in fact, our entire education system is not set up for proper education, but rather for proper economic training. This type of wisdom is not bad, as we can find similar ideas about wisdom in the biblical text (it is also not inherently good). Proverbs 1 says of those who ignore the call to be wise:

“I in turn will laugh when disaster strikes you;
    I will mock when calamity overtakes you—
     when calamity overtakes you like a storm,
    when disaster sweeps over you like a whirlwind,
    when distress and trouble overwhelm you….

    …. Since they would not accept my advice
    and spurned my rebuke,
     they will eat the fruit of their ways
    and be filled with the fruit of their schemes.                                                               

 For the waywardness of the simple will kill them,
    and the complacency of fools will destroy them;
but whoever listens to me will live in safety
    and be at ease, without fear of harm.”

We can see here that wisdom produces security and safety in its students. Wisdom is the study of success and living to minimize hardship.

Thus, wisdom is not the key to a good life. It is merely the way to an easy, effective one.

Too often we place decisions in the morality camp, when they more properly belong to the wisdom camp. Consider many Levitical laws regarding the governing of the Israelites. These laws were clearly meant for the practical purpose of teaching the Israelites how to effectively live in community as desert nomads thousands of years ago. Yet, they became sacralized and taken as moral law by the Jewish community. This moralizing, sacralizing process created the problems of 1st century Palestine that Jesus taught fervently against. The Sabbath was made for man, not man for the Sabbath.

Today we see this same moralization of actions more appropriately considered under the umbrella of wisdom just as much in our society. Hard work, buying a house (looking at us, millennials), and getting an education are all examples of life-decisions that we treat as though it were a matter of one’s moral standing. If one does not participate in any of these aspects of life, they are generally considered worthless. In reality none of these things are inherently good, and are only morally valuable when pointed to the correct goals. Wisdom is amoral, and assigning moral values to matters of wisdom produces cultural stratification and communities built around achievement and status. This community of wisdom-moral equivalence is self-defeating and falls straight into the trap of every cultural system ever: class-warfare.

Wisdom has its uses in morals though. If wise decisions are only made by chance, and we do not properly navigate the world around us, we are unusable for any purpose and cut ourselves off at the ankles in every decision. I’m sure we can all probably think of someone who has made unwise decisions recently and has become their own worst enemy. If we follow the morals of love and respect for all people, we should filter our actions through wisdom as well, or our love does more harm than good. If we do not have a healthy moral system, I strongly suggest that it is better to allow ourselves to crash and burn than accomplish our goals.

We should not idolize wisdom, for:

“I applied myself to the understanding of wisdom, and also of madness and folly, but I learned that this, too, is a chasing after the wind. For with much wisdom comes much sorrow….” – Ecclesiastes 1:17-18

Wisdom properly driven by morality is the most powerful force in accomplishing real good in the world. The moment wisdom climbs out of the back seat and starts telling morality how to drive, we run into problems. Wisdom is not a driver or an engine, it is the rubber on the road that propels the car forward.

Categories
Philosophy

Hegel’s Continuity with History and Contemporary Relevance

Throughout my education I have been in search of the perfect model by which to relate the world around me to myself. At various points throughout this process I have found answers and subsequently been faced by their impossibility. This movement between answer and negation followed the shape of postmodern deconstruction or Pyrrhonean skepticism until I found myself without any intellectual commitments and completely within myself. Yet, this was not and is not a viable stopping point for anyone, as the self in itself is just as unknowable as the objects outside the self. Little did I know that the shape of my intellectual development as a student followed not only a typical postmodern system, but also the shape of Western philosophy in general. Hegel, being a student of history, grasps the problem presented by Western philosophy and offers an interpretation and solution which has been largely misunderstood since his time.

This paper is an attempt to reverse engineer Hegel through his continuity with Western philosophy all the way from the pre-Socratics and present the relevance of his thought for humanity today. Unfortunately, the scope of this project necessitates that the analysis be inadequate in terms of its thoroughness. The goal is to present a wide, but merely cursory look through the history of philosophy towards Hegel. Along with this, the entire scope of Hegel’s work has not been considered, only those parts of Phenomenology of Spirit that seem essential to the project are treated. The limit of this project is also present in my treatment of Hegel’s ongoing relevance, in that our present is in constant development and is impossible to treat thoroughly.

Despite these limitations, I will show how Hegel solves the problem of philosophy as he understands it and why his understanding offers a viable solution to the problem as it has developed into the present. To begin, I will show what the problem or primary question of philosophy is and has been. Then I will trace the solutions to this problem through the Christian tradition, followed by a presentation of Hegel’s system with relevant ties back to philosophy and Christian tradition made explicit. Lastly I will present some contemporary Hegelians and show their reliance on Hegelian thought.

Presentation of the Problem: A Brief Overview of Western Philosophy

Western philosophy arguably begins with Thales, the earliest of the Ionians and the first to articulate the problem. Thales rather strangely thought that the universal substance was water and that the world had a soul which caused motion. The genius of Thales is not these assertions in particular but his being the first to articulate the problem. This problem is how the universal relates to the particular. For Thales, the universal waters are animated by soul, which is the essence of movement and thus particularity. By setting up the problem in this way, Thales set the course for the rest of Western philosophy.[1] Anaximander, Thales’ student extended this problem by arguing that the universal substance must be infinite since it must not be generated. Rather, the universal is that out of which all particulars are generated. It must be infinite because if it were limited it would have a beginning and thus would have been generated of something outside of itself and not be universal. He also thought that the universal was a principle or a law, not one of the fundamental elements.[2] Pythagoras carries this logic further by stating that nature is a harmony of those things which are limited and the universals which are unlimited. These harmonies are characterized by numbers, which are analogous to the universe. This division of nature into limited and unlimited in harmony led to his view of the human as a soul endlessly transported from body to body in death. Thus, the person or self is really the soul.[3]

Moving to the last of the Ionians, Heraclitus offers the first definite precursor to Hegel’s thought; Hegel wrote his thesis on Heraclitus.[4] The most famous of Heraclitus’ sayings is that “one cannot step twice into the same river, nor can one grasp any mortal substance in a stable condition, but it scatters and again gathers; it forms and dissolves, and approaches and departs.”[5] What is meant is this: particular substances, i.e. any individual thing, contains within their being their own constant changing. Thus, a river is only a river as it ceases to be the river it was and becomes the river it will be. Everything is in flux. This extends to our experience of life and death. Heraclitus points out the dialectic nature of life and death when he says, “for souls it is death to become water, for water it is death to become earth; out of earth water arises, out of water soul.” Death here functions as the instrument of change and regeneration in the universal, thus accounting for the particular while simultaneously denying the self-identity of the particular.[6]

While it might seem like Heraclitus has solved the problem prematurely, it is important to note that his account only works if you already hold certain ideas about the universal, such as its infinitude. Zeno, an Eleatic philosopher, critiques these assumptions and shows their logical impossibility. His primary insight is that infinitude cannot exist and be coherent with our experience of particulars; one could use Zeno to argue that reality is a simulation. The problem of infinity is most clearly critiqued in Zeno’s midway problem. This paradox states that for anything to move, i.e. for anything to be particular, it must complete an infinite number of tasks; because an infinite number of tasks is impossible to complete, movement must be impossible. This paradox operates on the assumption that between any two points are an infinite number of divisible points like a number line. Between 1 and 2 is 1.5, between 1 and 1.5 is 1.25, etc. ad infinitum.[7]

In reply to Zeno’s conclusion that nothing can move or change, Anaxagoras introduces the idea of a universal mind. This mind is infinite, immaterial, and all controlling. Functionally, the mind is no different than the idea of a simulated universe, for all particulars are merely ideas in the mind, or to put it in my words, the simulation. The programming of any given simulation never changes and encompasses all that is in the simulation, including the momentary activities of the subject being simulated. Thus, mind satisfies the relation of universal to particular by substantially destroying the particular and transforming it into the essence of the mind, however in order to accomplish this it must relinquish the idea that nature is real or actual.[8]

Protagoras takes this notion and develops it in a different direction. He says that “man is the measure of all things – of the things that are, that they are, and of the things that are not, that they are not.”[9] Instead of the mind being universal and particulars existing within it, here the mind is individual and the objects of its perception exist outside of it. This epistemological foundation is sufficient to establish the existence of the object in the mind of the observer, but it does nothing to establish the essence(s) of the object. Hence, all we have in Protagoras is the ability to know that things are, not what they are.[10]

The Three Shapes of Philosophy

Out of this groundwork, the three most important philosophers for understanding Western thought build their systems. These philosophers are Plato, Aristotle, and Sextus Empiricus. Plato develops the track established by Anaxagoras, Aristotle develops the track of Protagoras, and Empiricus acts as the negation of the entire project each of them attempt. Each of these tracks will from here on be referred to by their method of knowing: Plato is deductive, Aristotle is inductive, and Empiricus is skeptical.

The key of Plato’s philosophy is the theory of Forms, which are similar to Anaxagoras’ mind. Where Anaxagoras assumed the universal mind, Plato assumes a multitude of Forms, each self-contained and perfect, but relating to the sensuous world. The task of philosophy is to apprehend the Forms and apply them to particulars accurately. Each of the Forms is a predicate which can be applied to objects, e.g. the Form of Goodness can be applied to someone who is good.[11] In Hegelian terms, this type of reasoning can only be applied to things as they are in themselves, which is admitted by Plato himself in the dialogue Parmenides. In this dialogue, Parmenides critiques Socrates’ by arguing that Forms must be self-predicated, meaning that the Form of Good is also Good. These self-predicated Forms can be related to specific beings but fall into infinite regression since Forms are simply syllogisms. However, if Form is not self-predicated, then said Form cannot be related to specific beings because without the predicate, which is the substance of the Form, we have no means by which to apprehend the Forms.[12]

The key concept of Aristotle’s philosophy is the idea of substance, which is similar to Protagoras’ individual being the measure of all things. Instead of assuming some universal principle or being, Aristotle seats knowledge firmly in the sensuous experience of individual objects, which are called primary substances. Secondary substances are those categories that we apply to primary substances, like species or genus. Substance is not in a subject, only in an object, and these objects exist in flux or ‘receive contraries’.[13] In Hegelian terms, this type of epistemology is only able to apprehend things as they exist for themselves.

This brings us to Sextus Empiricus, who gives us the three categories of philosophy as we have divided them above. Platonic philosophy is called Academic, Aristotelian is called Dogmatic, and lastly there is the Skeptic. The Skeptic system forfeits the problem and refuses knowledge altogether, choosing instead to remain agnostic.[14] This system is best summed up in Empiricus’ own words:

It is also plain that all sensible are relative; for they are relative to those who have the sensations. Therefore it is apparent that whatever sensible object is presented can easily be referred to one of the Five Modes. And concerning the intelligible object we argue similarly. For if it should be said that it is a matter of unsettled controversy, the necessity of our suspending judgment will be granted. And if, on the other hand, the controversy admits of decision, then if the decision rests on an intelligible object we shall be driven to the regress ad infinitum, and to circular reasoning if it rests on a sensible; for since the sensible again is controverted and cannot be decided by means of itself because of the regress ad infinitum, it will require the intelligible object, just as also the intelligible will require the sensible. For these reasons, again, he who assumes anything by hypothesis will be acting illogically. Moreover, objects of thought, or intelligibles, are relative; for they are so named on account of their relation to the person thinking, and if they had really possessed the nature they are said to possess, there would have been no controversy about them.[15]

Thus, the pursuit of knowledge by any of these avenues has been thwarted by Empiricus’ logic and we are left at the start, unable to relate ourselves to the sensuous world except by pragmatism and without certainty. This problem would continue to be worked on, but after the advent of Christ, the question becomes altered. We will now trace its development through the Christian tradition.

The Problem in the Christian Tradition

Origen, the first Christian thinker I will examine, was committed to the deductive model of philosophy. According to him, all things began in divine unity (universality) and descended through sin into multiplicity (particularity). God ordered these things to work in their multiplicity for the service of the unity. Essentially, God has stepped into multiplicity so that the multiplicity can return upwards into unity.[16] Christ serves as the exemplary model of unity and division combined. His unity is as the Son of God, his multiplicity is as a rational human soul.[17] Origen also recognized the duality of consciousness, a primary interest of Hegel, in the division between flesh and spirit. However, Origen opposes them to each other so that the spirit is the superior of the two and the body is ultimately done away with.[18] The unique addition which Christian thought in Origen makes to the problem of Western philosophy is the unity of the division between God and Man, in that Christ exemplifies how division can be held in dialectic tension with unity.

Augustine, the primary figure in Western Christianity until Aquinas, continues this deductive track. Like Descartes, Augustine takes the individual consciousness as the foundation of knowledge. In remarkably Cartesian fashion, he says, “…if I am deceived, I am. For he who is not, cannot be deceived; and if I am deceived, by this same token I am.”[19] Yet, Augustine goes further and speaks of the soul “finding itself” as its own object.[20] Within this self, Augustine identifies three aspects, memory, understanding, and will, and relates each to the other such that they remain distinct, yet unified in the self. “For I remember that I have memory and understanding, and will; and I understand that I understand, and will, and remember; and I will that I will, and remember, and understand….”[21] Thus for the first time we have the triune nature of not God, but humanity, represented philosophically. This will become a model for Hegel.

Turning now to an earlier work called Soliloquies, we find Augustine’s dialogue with reason for the pursuit of knowledge regarding God. The first important revelation that Augustine articulates is that God is known in the same manner by which mathematics is known. Mathematics is known by the transformation of information taken in by the senses into intelligible truths which do not depend on reality.[22] Hegel will critique this model, but not outright reject its viability. The other key takeaway from Soliloquies is the dependence of predicates upon their subjects. For a predicate to exist, the subject upon which it is predicated must also exist, but the subject does not depend on the predicate unless that predicate contains the essence of the substance of the subject.[23] Here, without explicitly drawing from Aristotle, Augustine has managed to incorporate some of Aristotle’s key insights into his Platonism. These insights will be carried forward into Hegel.

Next we will look into Pseudo-Dionysius, an eclectic, mystic theologian. In his work The Divine Names, he offers an explanation of each of the names which we predicate upon God to explain his character. What sets Pseudo-Dionysius apart from other theologians of his time is his awareness of the depth of the division between God as God is in itself, and God as God acts for others. God in itself is entirely contentless, meaning that he is beyond any assertion or denial, simultaneously affirming and denying anything said by God’s very universality, similar to the problem of Plato’s Forms in Parmenides. Since nothing can correctly be predicated upon God as God is in itself, we can only know God as he exists for others.[24] Despite this, it is out of the very being of God in itself that everything comes to be and thus God in itself exists interdependently with Creation.[25]

Where Pseudo-Dionysius established the mystical understanding of God in itself, John Scotus Erigena develops the mystical understanding of humanity in itself. Just as God is beyond all assertion in denial, humanity is also beyond assertion and denial, “for that alone is a substantial definition, which affirms only that it is but negates that it is anything in particular.”[26] As a result of humanity in itself being beyond knowledge, it has itself as its object for contemplation. It is the task the human consciousness that knows that it is via Augustine’s logic to consider itself as outside itself because “…it knows that it is, but does not know what it is.”[27] This process is then extended to other humans in that, since the self exists in itself, that which exists in the understanding of both individuals unites them by their shared content. If one idea is understood in the same way by multiple people, then those people are identical where there understanding overlaps.[28] Thus, the other is brought into the self as one with the self.

We have here established the basic tools by which Hegel will construct his philosophy and attempt to solve the problem of Western philosophy. The problem is the inability of the universal to relate to the particular and our loss of certainty in that process. Since the foundation of any certainty is in the self, consciousness and the dialectic of unity and division become the ways in which this consciousness might be able to step outside of its subjectivity and become real. This is coming into actuality as self-consciousness, which requires an other, but in this we have still not solved the problem. We will now turn to Hegel, analyze his interpretation of the problem as stated above, and show his solution in what he calls Spirit.

Hegel Addresses the Problem

Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit is his most widely read work and establishes the foundations for his answer to the problem. He states as his goal, “that [philosophy] might be able to relinquish the name of love of knowledge and be actual knowledge.”[29] For Hegel, actual knowledge must exist in actuality, i.e. particularity. Thus, truth finds the form of its existence or actuality in science. This actuality of truth in science he calls the Concept. This science is against the type of knowing exemplified by deductive reasoning, which is intuition. Intuition knows the truth only as it is in itself, not as it pertains to the Concept. In a surprising twist, Hegel makes explicit that substance is the object of intuition, which is in agreement with what Sextus Empiricus thought was the downfall of deductive or Academic philosophy. As substance is the object of intuition, so is Concept the object of science.[30]

Formalism, which is taking any law as universal (think physics), is mere repetition of one simple Concept in several scenarios. Formalism cannot apprehend the absolute because it is not present in actuality via the same logical problems present in deductive philosophy. Any scenario which does not conform to the formula is written out of consideration as an anomaly, thus revealing that Formalism is mere repetition of a Form as a universal law. This cannot be knowledge because it does not pertain to the universal as it is in distinctness, which we will explore further later.[31] In this one swift motion, Hegel has done away with the dogmatic shape of philosophy by showing its reliance on the academic shape of philosophy, just as Empiricus did. What is revealed is that formulas as absolutes to explain all phenomena are Platonic, not Aristotelian. Thus, Physics is Platonic. Science as Formalism strips the universe of its life and leaves it as bare determinateness, subject to the universal system of the formula. Thus, substance is gotten rid of and the life of consciousness is robbed of its content. Science as Formalism provides merely the table of contents, not the contents themselves.[32]

The terms with which Hegel frames the problem is the inability of the subject to relate to the object, where the subject is the universal and the object is the particular. Thus, the absolute is subject, meaning God as a consciousness is the absolute. This absolute only becomes actual when it unites itself with substance or actuality. In Hegel’s words, “the living substance is… in truth actual only insofar as it is the movement of positing itself, or the mediation between a self and its development into something different.”[33] Here we clearly see the influence of Heraclitus, who said that everything is in flux. Thus, since God is defined as the absolute which becomes actual through self-mediation, we can divide the life of God into three moments: 1) it is in itself as the “circle that presupposes its end as its aim and thus has it for its beginning….”[34]This being in itself is only perceived by intuition, it is sameness and unity and abstract. This is the life of God as deductive yet unknowable, as it is in Pseudo-Dionysius and mystic theology. 2) It is for itself as Formalism, becoming, self-moving, mediating, and actual. This is the life of God as God acts. It is the realm of inductive philosophy and theology, as seen in Aristotle and the Scholastics. 3) Lastly, it is in and for itself, which is the sublimation of both forms of being in which both disappear.[35]

For now, Hegel deals with the first two alone, for the third cannot be understood without the first two. First, he addresses God as being in itself by writing on the names of God, much like Pseudo-Dionysius. God as a name is mere noise according to Hegel because it carries no content about God with it, and thus has no actuality. What the word signifies then is not a being or general principle, but God’s existence as that which is reflected back into itself, i.e. a subject. There is a problem with this idea of God though, and it is the same problem that Plato recognized in his theory of the Forms in Parmenides. “…that the absolute is subject is therefore not only not actuality of this Concept, but even makes this actuality impossible; for it posits a point at rest while the actuality is self-movement.”[36] It is important to remember here that Hegel is not pursuing knowledge of God, but rather he is attempting to establish a logic by which we may have knowledge of Truth. The goal is logical, not ontological.[37] It is because of this goal that God as being in itself will not satisfy the pursuit for truth.

Here Hegel surprisingly turns to his final goal: the idea of being in and for itself, which is Spirit, but we will have to return to this later, as it is the end in mind. Instead, we will demonstrate Hegel’s unique treatment of another kind of knowledge which is in itself: Math. His treatment of Math is important because it shows how he manages not to simply abandon being in itself. Math, according to Hegel, is insufficient for supplying knowledge in that it is merely internally consistent but not apprehended; this is the same problem Hegel has with God as a being in itself. Because Math concerns nothing but magnitude, and magnitude is not essential, it is devoid of Concept. It has no relation to matter, and thus has no actuality. Math cannot be comprehended in substances, and thus cannot be true except within itself. This is contrary to Augustine’s understanding of math/geometry, which serve him as analogous to our knowledge of God, but Augustine is committed to deductive philosophy which ends with being in itself.[38]

Hegel does not reject the truth of Math outright, he merely recognizes its place in the dialectic, which is to say that Math is a subject with no object apart from how it relates to objects for itself. In this turn, we will now consider Hegel’s understanding of being for itself. The best place to begin this consideration is in Hegel’s transition from being in itself to being for itself in the predicate of the being, a Pseudo-Dionysian move. The example Hegel provides is the proposition “God is being”. In this construction, subject and predicate become entangled, so that the subject disappears and the predicate becomes the subject, because the predicate “being” contains the subject within itself as far as the subject’s content goes. This is true of all subject-predicate constructions in which the predicate is the essence of the subject. Thus, the subject becomes an object unto (for) itself. With this we have stepped firmly into inductive, Aristotelian philosophy.[39]

Hegel critiques the inductive method along similar lines to what we would call the observer effect, although he takes it a step further into what would more rightly be called the knower effect. Because truth is absolute, knowing cannot be an instrument or medium by which we apprehend truth, because as an instrument or medium, knowing changes truth into something which it was not before, thus destroying the universality and content of the truth. In Aristotelian terms, the essence of the substance is lost in the knowing by way of the knowing not being an inherent part of the absolute. This treatment of knowledge as a philosophical subject to be understood transforms knowledge into an object for us. Knowledge itself is the object of our understanding. In this, knowledge and our understanding of it become a part of us in the same logic that Erigena used to say that where two people’s understandings overlapped they become one. In our perception of knowledge as an object for us, we have become unable to perceive knowledge in itself. Yet, in recognizing the object as an other, we acknowledge its existence and can compare the object as it is in itself with our understanding of it as it is for us.[40]

This acknowledgement is the foundation of Hegel’s treatment of consciousness, which will move us toward his solution in Spirit. Consciousness knows something as the object in itself, but this object is consciousness itself (this is often veiled from our consciousness). Thus, there are two objects in the self: the object in itself, and the being for consciousness of the in itself. The object in itself is the consciousness’ knowing of the object reflected back at the consciousness as in a mirror, but this reflection back changes the object into the being for consciousness of the in itself.[41] This is similar to Erigena’s construction of humanity in that the self knows that it is, but not what it is.[42] Restated in Hegel’s terms, Erigena says that humanity knows itself in itself but not for itself. Since this first object is knowledge, it is acknowledgement that gives rise to consciousness and also to the change of consciousness into something new, or mediation of the consciousness. This experience of the movement of consciousness is an attempt at science which is the science of the experience of consciousness.

Thus, knowledge has been established, but only knowledge of our own being. However, since consciousness has been established inductively, we can start to establish its relation to universals and have true Concept. This is counterintuitively established through sensuous experience. Because all sense experience refers to particulars like here and now through the ego or the I, sense experience becomes an internally limited universal. This is due to the terms themselves syllogistically being universal. Each of the terms, here, now, and I refer to particulars but it is impossible to refer to the terms themselves as particulars. The immediate relation of subject to object in these terms brings the object into the subject, transforming the inductive method into the deductive and placing our philosophy back into the deductive mode, or pure intuition. It is Formalism again.[43]

To explain more clearly, this is due to the internal infinitude of our terms. This infinitude arises out of the self-negation of the terms, much like Heraclitus’ river. Take the term now: a particular now has the essence of its predicates, for instance, day, but the essence of now is to change into a been. The now has become a been: it has been day, but it is not now. So, we can define now as that which is the be no more. There is no particular now, only an infinite multiplicities of particular nows. Thus, now is universal in that it negates itself. The same can be said of here and I. All three contain their own negation, for there is no “I”, only that “I” which has been, but the “I” is that very change from being to nonbeing, thus the “I” is reinstated as an absolute.[44] What Zeno said was true, anything with an infinite nature destroys its particularity, but Zeno failed to realize that if the essence of the thing is its own negation, the thing becomes universal. It is what is in itself. This gets us closer because it defines the nature of consciousness as that which is a series of moments, always becoming, but it is still stuck in itself. It is a limited infinity.

Because things which are unified are negative by way of their infinitude, they are also divided into particularities which assert themselves in order for the infinite to exist. So, unity and division are interrelated dialectically. The entirety of this process is Life; unity alone is not life, division alone is not life. They must be taken together as a whole, despite being diametrically opposed. Here enters the last step on our way to Spirit: self-consciousness. Consciousness desires certainty of itself, the subject, by the destruction of the object. In this construction, the subject is the infinite nature of “I” and the object is the particular “I”. The desire for certainty of the subject requires the object to destroy. This certainty is what constitutes self-consciousness. The desire is generated by the object, destroys the object, and regenerates the object through its desire. The object, containing its negation within itself, fulfills the desire of the subject in itself, and yet maintains itself by its independence from the subject. Self-consciousness is the immediate “I” as object, the mediation of the “I” by its immediacy (like here and now), and the desire to be truth which is reflected back into self-consciousness. Thus, self-consciousness is being for itself.[45]

Finally, we can see Hegel’s solution in Spirit, being in and for itself coming together. To recap briefly, being in itself is analogous with deductive philosophy and falls to the problems of Academic philosophy as articulated in Parmenides and by Sextus Empiricus, being for itself is analogous with inductive philosophy and falls to the problems of Dogmatic philosophy as articulated by Empiricus. Neither can reach true actuality or universality.

Hegel’s Solution: Spirit

The spiritual alone is the actual; it is [i] the essence or being-in-itself; [ii] that which relates itself and is determinate, that which is other and for itself; and [iii] that which in this determinateness and being outside itself remains in itself – or in other words, it is in and for itself…. The spirit that, so developed, knows itself as spirit is science. Science is the actuality of the spirit and the realm that the spirit builds for itself in its own element.[46]

The statement above is, in my assessment, the pinnacle of Idealist logic, and it is primarily this logic that I have been exploring thus far. I have made the claim that Hegel exists in continuity with the Christian tradition, but here I will take a bolder stance; Hegel’s logic here is orthodox Christian logic. At the council of Chalcedon, Christ’s nature as both divine and human held in tension was made explicit against the heresies of Arianism and Apollinarianism. Arianism took the stance that Christ was created and not truly divine, whereas Apollinarianism took the stance that Christ had a human body and a divine mind. Both arise out of a logic of false oppositions and Chalcedon, taken as a logical argument, refutes the logic of false oppositions. The Chalcedonian formula states that Christ had both natures, human and divine, and that both are preserved in their unity in Christ. This is identical with Hegel’s formulation of Spirit above as far as their governing logics go.[47]

Thus, the solution to the problem of knowledge, that which, in Hegel’s words can get us to Absolute Knowing, is the recognition and dissolution of false oppositions. This is precisely what the dialectic is. I have heard the dialectic explained as a thesis and antithesis diametrically opposed producing a synthesis by their conflict, but this explanation does not do justice to the revolutionary nature of this logic. It can be better stated that the dialectic, out of which we get Spirit, is the unity of the thesis and antithesis by their interdependent relationship. This does not do away with oppositional logic in all cases, but it does limit truth to those claims which are perceived via Spirit. Oppositional logic is not done away with in cases where two things have no relation to each other, rather, oppositional logic is done away with in cases in which two things are in inseparable relation, e.g. race, sex, religion, etc.[48]

The genius of Hegel is that he seats Spirit firmly in the experience of self-consciousness and humanity. Is it applied to God? Yes, but it is not limited to God, for that would be to exploit oppositional logic. Spirit is required to bridge the gap not only between humanity and God, but also between individuals and their world

Contemporary Significance

To conclude this project I will show how Hegel is still present in contemporary Christian thought through two vastly different authors. Terence Fretheim, who is a Biblical scholar of the Old Testament and is fairly conservative, and Peter Rollins who is a liberal, radical theologian.  My choice of these two is intentional to reflect the false opposition between conservative biblical theology and liberal radical theology. They are not opposed, rather, they are distinct but in interdependent relationship.

Fretheim’s focus is on creation theology, and his interpretation of the creation accounts in Genesis 1-2 exhibits Hegelian logic perfectly. Whereas the traditional interpretation of God’s creative act is that God is the sole actor on Creation, one could interpret God’s creative act as in dialog with creation. “…the divine creating often entails a speaking with that which is already created…. God’s creative act is mediated in and through these creatures…. Hence, the divine speaking in this chapter is of such a nature that the receptor of the word is important in the shaping of the created order.”[49] For Fretheim, this means that God by his very nature, exists in dialectic with Creation.

This is made permanent in his covenant with Noah, in which God permanently limits his ability to intervene in the natural outcomes of evil, which is defined as the undoing of the creative work. “For God to promise not to do something again entails an eternal self-limitation regarding the exercise of divine freedom and power. God thereby limits the divine options in dealing with evil in the life of the world…. Genesis 6:5-7 makes the bold claim that this kind of divine response means that God will take the route of suffering. For God to decide to endure a wicked world, while continuing to open up the divine heart to that world, means that God’s grief is ongoing.”[50] Initially it was by God’s nature that Creation was allowed to exist in union with the divine creative act, now it is by God’s promise that Creation is allowed to exist as an opposing force against God. Thus, Creation is in an interdependent relationship with God; God by his nature must create the world, while the world by its existence relies on God. Yet, by its freedom, the world has become opposed to God. Jesus becomes the embodiment of Spirit, or the synthesis of this dialectic. This synthesis is explored by Peter Rollins in The Divine Magician.

The problem, which is identified as sin by Rollins, is the false opposition of the divinity and humanity. We look to the divine as that which can fulfill us but fail to recognize that the divine is the very lack which we seek to fill. This is solved by Christ, in that Christ makes the gap or lack within God explicit.[51] This presentation of the object which we think will bring us fulfillment and the subsequent disappearance of that object is what Rollins calls the divine magic trick. “This change in perspective means that heaven and earth are no longer seen as separate, but the sacred and profane are fused, and the pursuit of a single fruit-bearing tree is replaced with the vision of an abundant world ready for harvest.”[52] The reappearance of the object which was made to disappear is the loss of the sacred object which we thought could fulfill us and the embracing of the lack within us as that which unites us with God.[53]

Conclusion

Like a magic trick, that dogmatic certainty with which I began my education was made to disappear in the various perspectives and criticisms which I came in contact with, most of which have been touched on in this paper. Whether or not Hegelian logic can adequately serve as the foundation for the reappearance of faith is not the question which I am attempting to answer, but it is the one I want to leave with those on a similar path. Knowledge in either of its two typical forms must be done away with to make space for Spirit, yet the forms of knowledge in Plato and Aristotle are nothing anyway. They are not vehicles for truth, and thus are not true knowledge. Two terms which Hegel takes as a pair are thinking and being. I have been told that the purpose of education is to teach one how to think, but when operating as a Hegelian, it could also be stated as “the purpose of education is to teach one how to be.”

Works Cited

Adams, Nicholas. The Eclipse of Grace: Divine and Human Action in Hegel. New Jersey: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013.

Augustine. Soliloquies. Translated by Kim Paffenroth. New York: New City Press, 2014.

Fretheim, Terence E. God and World in the Old Testament: A Relational Theology of Creation. Nashville: Abingdon Press, 2005.

Inwood, M. J., ed. Hegel: Selections. New York: Macmillan, 1989.

Kolak, Daniel, and Garrett Thomson. The Longman Standard History of Ancient Philosophy. New York: Pearson Longman, 2006.

Kolak, Daniel, and Garrett Thomson. The Longman Standard History of Medieval Philosophy. New York: Pearson Longman, 2006.

Origen. On First Principles. Translated by G. W. Butterworth. New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1966.

Pseudo-Dionysius. Pseudo-Dionysius: The Complete Works. Translated by Colm Luibheid. New York: Paulist Press, 1987.

Rollins, Peter. The Divine Magician: The Disappearance of Religion and the Discovery of Faith. New York: Howard, 2015.

[1] Daniel Kolak, & Garrett Thomson, The Longman Standard History of Ancient Philosophy (New York: Pearson Longman, 2006), 8-9.

[2] Ibid, 10-11.

[3] Kolak & Thomson, Ancient Philosophy, 16-19.

[4] Ibid, 29.

[5] Ibid, 24.

[6] Ibid, 24-30.

[7] Kolak & Thomson, Ancient Philosophy, 37-38.

[8] Ibid, 50-53.

[9] Ibid, 64.

[10] Ibid, 64-65.

[11] Kolak & Thomson, Ancient Philosophy, 74.

[12] Ibid, 254-255.

[13] Kolak & Thomson, Ancient Philosophy, 278-280.

[14] Ibid, 495.

[15] Ibid, 500.

[16] Origen, On First Principles, trans. G. W. Butterworth (New York: Harper and Row, 1966), 77.

[17] Ibid, 111-112.

[18] Ibid, 234-235.

[19] Daniel Kolak, & Garrett Thomson, The Longman Standard History of Medieval Philosophy (New York: Pearson Longman, 2006), 29.

[20] Kolak & Thomson, Medieval Philosophy, 30-31.

[21] Ibid, 33.

[22] Augustine, Soliloquies, trans. Kim Paffenroth (New York: New City Press, 2000), 29-32.

[23] Ibid, 78-79.

[24] Pseudo-Dionysius, Pseudo-Dionysius: The Complete Works, trans. Colm Lubheid (New York: Paulist Press, 1987), 50.

[25] Ibid, 54.

[26] Kolak & Thomson, Medieval Philosophy, 103.

[27] Ibid, 105.

[28] Ibid, 112.

[29] M. J. Inwood, ed., Hegel: Selections (New York: Macmillan, 1989), 117.

[30] Ibid, 117-119.

[31] Inwood, Hegel, 121-122.

[32] Ibid, 139-140.

[33] Ibid, 123.

[34] Ibid, 123.

[35] Inwood, Hegel, 123.

[36] Ibid, 125.

[37] Nicholas Adams, Eclipse of Grace: Divine and Human Action in Hegel (New Jersey: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013), 9.

[38] Inwood, Hegel, 135.

[39] Ibid, 145.

[40] Inwood, Hegel, 153-158.

[41] Ibid, 159.

[42] Kolak & Thomson, Medieval Philosophy, 103.

[43] Inwood, Hegel, 164.

[44] Inwood, Hegel, 165-166.

[45] Ibid, 171-175.

[46] Inwood, Hegel, 126.

[47] Adams, Eclipse of Grace, 5-7.

[48] Adams, Eclipse of Grace, 23-24.

[49] Terence E. Fretheim, God and World in the Old Testament: A Relational Theology of Creation (Nashville: Abingdon Press, 2005), 38.

[50] Ibid, 83.

[51] Peter Rollins, The Divine Magician: The Disappearance of Religion and the Discovery of Faith (New York: Howard, 2015), 69-70.

[52] Ibid, 157.

[53] Ibid, 120.